wp cardoso

17
Máster en Democracia y Gobierno Departamento de Ciencia Política y Relaciones Internacionales Universidad Autónoma de Madrid A a Working Papers Online Series www.uam.es/wpcpolitica Estudio/Working Paper 131/2011 “From Human Rights to Multiculturalism and Back” João Cardoso Rosas University of Minho, Postugal [email protected] C P Seminario de Investig ación I X 2010-2011 1

Upload: gonzalo-farrera

Post on 23-May-2017

212 views

Category:

Documents


0 download

TRANSCRIPT

Page 1: Wp Cardoso

Máster en Democracia y Gobierno

Departamento de Ciencia Política y

Relaciones Internacionales

Universidad Autónoma de Madrid

A a

Working Papers Online Series www.uam.es/wpcpolitica

Estudio/Working Paper 131/2011

“From Human Rights to

Multiculturalism and Back”

João Cardoso Rosas

University of Minho, Postugal

[email protected]

C P

Seminario de

Investig ación

I

X

2010-2011

1

Page 2: Wp Cardoso

This paper describes three stages in the connection between human rights and

multiculturalism and it adds a fourth one. These four stages are roughly chronological, but

they are first and foremost of a conceptual character. In the first stage, human rights and

multiculturalism stand in opposition. This corresponds to the immediately post-II World War

context. In the second stage, during the nineteen eighties, multiculturalism is made

compatible with human rights by the work of philosophers such as Will Kymlicka (among

others). Although multiculturalism has become acceptable as a political practice in several

European countries since then, it started to be repelled in the name of human rights since the

nineties - and, particularly, during the first decade of the twenty-first century - by both

philosophers and politicians. This is the third stage. I propose and defend a fourth and

current stage, which should be called “post-multiculturalist”, in which the language of

universal human rights is used in order to accommodate cultural and other differences. This

stage differs from the second one insofar as it departs from the defence of multicultural

rights, preferring instead to show how the demands of ethnic diversity can be answered

without resorting to conceptions of special rights and exemptions for minorities.

Stage 1: Human rights and multiculturalism stand in opposition

The expression “human rights” convokes a vast semantic field. Very often, people confuse

human rights with natural rights, or citizenship rights. Both the traditions of the natural

rights of man and of citizenship rights were certainly important in the historical evolution of

the idea of human rights. However, the contemporary meaning of human rights emerged in

Paris, in 1948, when the Universal Declaration of Human Rights was voted at the Palais de

Chaillot.

Human rights, then, are those subjective “claim rights” declared by the United Nations in

1948, as well as those that were added by posterior declarations and treaties. In particular,

the content of human rights is specified by the Covenant on Civil and Political Rights and

the Covenant on Social, Economic and Cultural Rights, both from 1966. Moreover, human

rights are also specified by several other documents in international law dealing with

particular categories of rights (for the abolition of slavery, against discrimination in

education, for equal remuneration for men and women, et cetera), as well as documents

regarding specific categories of people (stateless persons, refugees, women, children,…). All

2

Page 3: Wp Cardoso

these arise in the framework of United Nations system and they are consistent with the

Universal Declaration.

Furthermore, human rights are also stated at the regional level, as in the case of the Council

of Europe and the European Convention for the Protection of Human Rights and

Fundamental Freedoms. Finally, the protection of human rights at the state level is also

extremely important. This includes the rights that sates may accord to every human being in

their territory but also, with less impact internationally, the so-called fundamental rights

usually enshrined in the Constitution, which may be seen as a local application of the idea of

human rights in international public law.

This being said, human rights are a legal concept. But this point does not imply any kind of

legal positivism. One can easily link the idea of human rights affirmed in 1948 and after with

basic moral ideas, such as “intrinsic dignity” of human beings, equality, and the generality

and universality of those rights. Whether or not these rights and underlying principles require

further and deeper foundations is something that I will address below. The consensus among

the drafters of the Universal Declaration and the members of the UNESCO committee

charged with exploring the philosophical foundations of human rights was that agreement on

the list of rights was feasible, but there was no agreement whatsoever regarding the deeper

justification of those rights. The famous phrase mentioned by Jacques Maritain in the

“Introduction” to the proceedings of the UNESCO committee sums it all. He said: “Yes, we

agree about the rights, but on condition no one asks us why”.

Now this model of human rights – let us call it “the model 48” - does not include

multiculturalist concerns. I take multiculturalism in a strong sense, i.e., as requiring

multicultural rights in order to protect both ethnic and national minorities. If

multiculturalism were to signify the vague idea of distributing some resources to institutions

claiming to represent minorities in order, for instance, to subsidize festivals and the like, then

this would not be very relevant and it would not require careful discussion. Multiculturalist

demands become important whenever they affect and change the legal system requiring, for

instance, special representation rights, or other legal rights and immunities aimed at the

protection of cultural minorities. This is what multicultural rights are about. In 1948 and in

the documents consistent with the model 48 there is no room for multiculturalism in this

sense. Why is this?

3

Page 4: Wp Cardoso

The drafters of the Universal Declaration and other documents in line with the model 48

were certainly aware of the multicultural character of the world as a whole and of many

independent sates. Nevertheless, they decided to adopt a list of rights blind-folded towards

cultural diversity.

Ethnic and national divisions had been at the centre of World War II. Recall that the Nazi

aggression was justified on racist basis and on the need of “Lebensraum” for the German

people. More specifically, the Nazis invoked the Minority Treaties that protected German

minorities with multicultural rights in Poland and Czechoslovakia. Because of these events,

the idea of special protections for minorities was discredited in the aftermath of the war.

Moreover, “the final solution for the Jewish question”, the Nazi euphemism for the Shoa,

and the very idea of the supremacy of the German people, were also based on racist and

ethnic considerations. In the aftermath of the war, after the full disclosure of the horrendous

crimes perpetrated by the Nazis, it seemed better to emphasize the unity of the human kind,

rather than its divisions. Therefore, the Universal Declaration states in its Preamble “the

inherent dignity” and the “equal and inalienable rights of all members of the human family”,

regardless of their cultural belonging. This is the spirit of 48.

The prevailing mood favourable to human rights and hostile to multicultural rights was

continued during the cold war. In this context, both the western Block and the Communist

countries were engaged in a geo-political struggle supported by ideologies, which were, by

and large, favourable to some form of equal rights and citizenship and suspicious towards

multicultural rights and differentiated citizenship.

In the West, the prevailing ideology was the defence of liberal-democracy with an emphasis

on the respect for fundamental freedoms and basic rights at the domestic level and

internationally. Much of the critique directed against the Communist countries was based on

their disrespect for human rights, particularly, civil rights such as freedom of expression,

association and reunion, and the right to political participation. Even the social movements at

the domestic level of Western countries were asking for access to equal rights – by black

people, by women, etc. – and not really for the recognition of their differences.

4

Page 5: Wp Cardoso

In the Communist world, the prevailing ideology was Marxism, perhaps not always the

thought of Karl Marx, but at least the version usually called “Vulgar Marxism”. In this

framework, the only relevant divisions in society are social classes, not cultures. The

simplification of the class structure in bourgeois society leads to the contradiction between

the capital and the proletariat. Marx himself was clear in stating that the capital has no

homeland and the same applies to the working class. Belonging to a specific nation or ethnic

group was invisible in the light of Marxist categories. The aim of history was the elimination

of private property and the end of the class structure of society. This would be enough to

resolve all conflicts.

In so far as human rights are concerned, the contribution of Marxism was extremely relevant

even in the drafting of the Universal Declaration, emphasising the importance of social and

economic rights. In line with this, the counter-accusation that Communist countries used to

direct to the West pointed to the disrespect by liberal-democracies of those economic and

social rights. However, the Communist world was convergent with the West in the neglect of

multicultural rights and multicultural demands. The prevailing ideologies in the two blocks

agreed on this, even when disagreeing in almost everything else.

The opposition between human rights and multiculturalism, immediately after WWII and

beyond, is acknowledged by Will Kymlicka since his book on Liberalism, Community and

Culture. However, Kymlicka claims that this opposition is contingent and it actually goes

against the liberal tradition and the consensus among nations before WWII. As he writes:

“post war liberal clichés [about the opposition between human rights and multiculturalism]

need to be rethought, for they misrepresent the issue, and the liberal tradition itself” (p.211).

So, one aspect to take into consideration is the liberal tradition, which, before WW II used to

stress the commonality of the individual human being. Kymlicka finds this kind of approach

in the work of John Stuart Mill, T. H. Green, Hobhouse and Dewey. These authors were not

communitarians, but they were concerned with cultural membership and its protection as

part and parcel of the idea of the just society.

The other aspect that Kymlicka wants to put in evidence is the dominant political consensus

before WW II, in the framework of the League of Nations (Société des Nations). The

question of the protection of minorities was extremely relevant in this context, both at the

5

Page 6: Wp Cardoso

domestic level of sates and internationally. The attribution of minority rights and treaties

drafted to ensure them was the current business of politics.

So, Kymlicka sees his own approach as a form of reviving the multiculturalist tradition

within liberal thought and political practice. However, in the context of the eighties or

nineties, he and other multiculturalists had to reconcile the claim for multicultural rights with

the prevailing culture of human rights. This point leads to a second stage in the relationship

between human rights and multiculturalism.

Stage 2: Making human rights and multiculturalism compatible

The shift towards making compatible human rights and multiculturalist demands started with

the ethnic revival still in the context of the Cold War (in some places, this revival may have

taken place later: for instance in the eighties and nineties). In any case, the claim of

multiculturalists is that, at some point, social movements and social groups started to ask for

the protection of their specific identities. Charles Taylor has provided the Hegelian language

of recognition to make sense of that shift, particularly in his influential paper on “The

Politics of Recognition” (in Amy Gutman (ed.), Multiculturalism).

According to Taylor, the struggles for recognition in the modern state were, in a first

moment, about access to equal citizenship. Groups excluded from citizenship, or

discriminated against in terms of rights of citizenship, demanded to be included. This

political logic applied to ethnic and national groups, as well as to others kinds of

marginalized identities (women, for instance). Taylor calls this “the politics of equal

dignity”.

Now the politics of equal dignity at the state level square well with human rights in the

model 48. The equal stand of all human beings in their human rights and the equal stand of

all the citizens in their fundamental rights are two aspects of the same promotion of “equal

dignity”. However, recognition through the politics of equal dignity became ever insufficient

once ethnic, national and other groups started to make visible their demands to be recognized

also in their differences, including through the attribution of multicultural rights.

6

Page 7: Wp Cardoso

In order to capture this movement in history, Taylor suggests that “the politics of

difference”, although apparently in contradiction with the politics of equal dignity, is in fact

a development of the same modern desire to be recognized. After a first moment in which

recognition implied equal dignity, comes the second moment in which equal dignity is

maintained, but it is not enough anymore. In this second moment – perhaps the one we are

still living in – equal dignity is complemented by the politics of difference. Besides being

recognized as holders of the same rights, the members of different cultural communities

want to be recognized in their specificity and to see the collective ends of their communities

protected by differentiated rights.

Taylor complements his defence of the politics of difference with ideas regarding the prima

facie equal value of cultures, and also with the hermeneutic view regarding the dialogue of

cultures and a “fusion of horizons”. I don’t have time to get into that here. I just want to

point to the fact that Taylor’s language of recognition, equal dignity and difference provides

the dominant vocabulary for the paradigm of stage 2, i.e., the idea that human rights and

mutlticulturalism are compatible - they are as compatible as equal dignity and the politics of

difference.

This ability to reach a synthesis of two opposing views – namely human rights and

multiculturalism - at a very high level of abstraction is one of the features of Taylor’s work.

Nevertheless, even when the opposition is resolved in high theory, it tends to remain in

social reality. The devil is always in the practical details.

I think that Kymlicka’s work goes much further than Taylor’s in dealing with the practical

details and, therefore, in giving a more compelling version of the compatibility thesis than

Taylor’s. I am not going to summarize Will’s argument in favour of multicultural rights in

Multicultural Citizenship and after. I just want to recall the fact that his argument is

distinguishably liberal, since it is based on the protection of the values of choice and liberty.

The societal culture to which individuals are attached is a social primary good (in the sense

of Rawls) because it is this context that gives specific content to the individual choices. This

context needs to be protected by multicultural rights whenever it is endangered by the

pressure of the predominant culture.

7

Page 8: Wp Cardoso

Kymlicka accepts human rights and equal rights of citizenship for all, but he adds that other

rights – namely multicultural rights – are needed in order to protect the societal culture of

minorities, whether they are national or ethnic. He enters into details by pointing out

different kinds of multicultural rights – self-government rights, polyethnic rights, special

representation rights – and establishing that not all those rights, or kinds of rights, are

required to protect all kinds of cultural minorities. For instance, national minorities usually

require self-government, whereas ethnic minorities ask for polyethnic rights, such as legal

immunities to protect traditional forms of life, or specific religious practices.

Because, unlike Taylor, Kymlicka enters into details he has to deal with the difficulties that

arise at the sociological and practical level. He is well aware that some of the demands of

cultural groups enter in conflict with the baseline of equality defined by general and

universal fundamental rights or human rights. He knows that anti-multiculturalists always

bring into discussion some multiculturalist demands that are difficult to accept, such as

female genital mutilation, arranged marriages, and the like. So, he has to draw the line

between “good” multicultural rights and “bad” multicultural rights. To do that, he

distinguishes between “external protections” and “internal restrictions”. I would like to focus

your attention for a while in this distinction.

Multicultural rights are always protections against external pressures coming from the

majority’s culture, against the minorities. As external protections, multicultural rights allow

the minorities to maintain their societal culture in time – even if this culture is always

evolving – and therefore, to protect the context of choice of their members. However,

multicultural rights, in the sense of Kymlicka, should not be internal restrictions to the

fundamental rights and freedoms of minority cultures. In short: multicultural rights should be

added to human rights, but without endangering the latter.

The conceptual distinction between external protections and internal restrictions is useful,

but it does not allow for easy decisions about which rights should be admitted as

multicultural rights. For instance, self-government rights in non-liberal communities (e.g., an

indigenous nation in America) may lead to the suspension of the Bill of Rights that is legally

binding for everyone else. In this case, self-government rights should not be admitted as

multicultural rights. But that is not what Kymlicka and other liberal multiculturalists say.

They prefer to think that it is acceptable to grant that kind of special status as a form of

8

Page 9: Wp Cardoso

protecting the minority cultures against the laws and the Courts of the central state, even

when this state abides by international standards of human rights.

Now let us turn to the possibility of legal exemptions to protect the practice of polygamy by

some cultural minorities. Most liberal multiculturalists would say that this is unacceptable

because it breaches the principle of equality of men and women inside the family.

Nevertheless, the practice of polygamy may be extremely relevant for a community’s

identity and it may be defended as a voluntary option for adult men and women. So, it is at

least disputable that polygamy should not be accepted as an external protection and a

morally required multicultural right. I do not mean here that polygamy is acceptable, but

rather that I do not see why liberal multiculturalists should necessarily object to it.

These two examples – the illiberal self-governed community inside a liberal state and the

claim for legal immunity to polygamous marriages in an ethnic group – suggests that the

distinction between external protections and internal restrictions is not clear-cut and, what is

more, its application leads to argument based not in principles but in intuitions case by case.

Sometimes – like in the case of the illiberal nation – it is ok to limit fundamental rights, or to

suspend their application and legal protection. Some other times – as in the case of polygamy

in a given minority – it is not ok because it goes against the human rights view of equality

between men and women. So, in the first case liberal multiculturalists tend to be more

multiculturalist than liberal whereas in the second case they are usually more liberal than

multiculturalist.

Other examples could be given. But these two are enough to show that there is some

problem here. It seems to me that he culturalist view, by introducing the intrinsic value of

communal belonging, cannot but shake the idea of equal standing of all human beings

conveyed by the human rights approach, at least in the model 48. Accordingly, the

compatibility between human rights and multiculturalism advocated by liberal

multiculturalists is made at a price, namely, the departure from the strict advocacy of human

rights in the model 48 and the resort to intuition and casuistry in defining the exact shape of

that departure.*

* Kymlicka seems to believe that liberal democracies and human rights abiding regimes are solid-rock, that they will never be perturbed by less liberal forms of multiculturalism. I do not buy that.

9

Page 10: Wp Cardoso

I believe that this lack of clarity among multiculturalists – even liberal multiculturalists –

regarding the protection of equal human rights has led to the erosion of the appeal of the

multiculturalist view, at least in Europe. This point leads to a next stage.

Stage 3: Moving away from multiculturalism in Europe

A third model regarding the relationship between multiculturalism and equal rights has

grown strong in Europe in recent years. This model is anti-multiculturalist, it is linked to a

number of practices and it is supported by theory. This model, usually called “civic

integration”, is now the prevailing view in European countries and also at the European

Union level.

In Europe, multiculturalism has been perceived as a Canadian story. There’s some truth in

this. Canada was the first country to develop consistent multiculturalist policies. Canada

even constitutionalised its multicultural character. It is not an accident that the two single

most influential thinkers on theses issues, Taylor and Kymlicka, are Canadian. Canadian

multiculturalism could be seen in a sympathetic way by some European countries with heavy

immigration contingents, particularly the Netherlands and, later, the United Kingdom, and

also by minority nations within unitarian sates, such as Catalonia or the Basque Country in

Spain.

Some historic nations in Europe acceded to self-government rights, increasing their

autonomy. This kind of processes is highly contested insofar as it implies a high price for

those who do not identify with the majority culture within the minority sub-unit (ex: non

Catalans, or non-nationalist Catalans in Catalunya). However, this kind of problems is not

usually associated with multiculturalism and the word is reserved to the politics dealing with

ethnic diversity, as opposed to multinationality. The decline of multiculturalism in Europe I

refer to here regards public policies dealing with migrants and their descendants, more than

historic nations.

In the European sense, multiculturalism is part of the political experience in the Netherlands

and, later, in the United Kingdom. Confronted with high levels of immigration, these

countries adopted the idea that immigrant communities could see their cultural practices,

10

Page 11: Wp Cardoso

religion, language, etc. protected by law and still be part of the global society, or be one of

the pillars of the global society in those countries. However, these feeble multiculturalist

attempts are now over.

The perception that multiculturalist policies in these countries were not really working as an

instrument of integration of immigrants in the host society grew progressively since the

nineties and it reached its peak around 2004-05. These dates are symbolic in the sense that

they mark a dramatic non-returning point in the drifting away from multiculturalism in

Europen politics.

2004 is the year of the killing of movie maker Theo Van Gogh in Amsterdam. This event

and its exemplar character is well described by Ian Buruma. Buruma links the death of Van

Gogh – and the persecution to Hirsi Ali - to the backlash of Dutch multiculturalism. The

general perception in this country is that multiculturalist policies created the guethos of

resentment that made possible the killing of Van Gogh. The solution for this situation, then,

would be to require that immigrants show a more pro-active integration in Dutch society and

the respect of Dutch values.

2005 is the year of the terrorist attacks in the London transport system. Again in this case,

multiculturalist policies were blamed for the erosion of the sense of community, of

Britishness. The idea that different communities could stand apart in British society, and

with their differences protected by law, could not be easily accepted anymore. Since then,

multiculturalism is under fire also in this country.

Now this public perception and the link between multiculturalist policies and gethoisation,

and political violence, may be purely self-deceiving. Nevertheless, it a watershed for the

European experience of Canadian-like multicultural policies. This public perception also

makes anti-multiculturalism more attractive as a theory and it leads to the model that is now

prevailing in Europe, namely “civic integration”.

Communitarian and nationalist anti-multiculturalism are the driving forces behind the idea of

civic integration. The current tendency in most European countries – and with the support of

the institutions of the European Union – is to require immigrants to study the history and

culture of their host countries, to attend naturalization ceremonies in order to become

11

Page 12: Wp Cardoso

citizens, to sign declarations of compromise with the constitutional values of the host

countries, and even to give up ostensive cultural and religious symbols and practices (the

hijab, the minarets). To my mind, this kind of practices reveals, with all evidence, that the

so-called “civic integration model” is rather a form of cultural assimilation by which

immigrants have to integrate in the host society not by maintaining their differences but

rather by cleaning the canvas of their lives and start afresh. The civic integration model

requires ethnic groups to keep their differences to themselves and to give up their expression

in the political domain and in the public square.

The French Republican model may be taken as an old example of civic integration. French

republican ideology was never prone to multiculturalism and it always required the

immigrants to adhere to the values of republicanism and laicism. In the French ideology,

these requirements are seen as universal values. But that is an illusion. They are very

peculiar to the French experience. They are communitarian values understandable in the

light of contemporary French history and, in same cases – such as the prohibition of the hijab

– they are also illiberal. However, the relevant question is whether or not the French model,

and civic integration in general, work better than multiculturalism.

Returning to the field of public perceptions, one should remind that civic integration has no

better record than multicultural policies. In the same year of 2005, when the London

bombings occurred, the peripheries of Paris and other French cities were in fire. Some of the

reactions in French society were no less strong than in the UK. There was a sensation of

gethoization as the result of previous policies. This situation is paradoxical: civic integration

seems to work as badly as multiculturalism. According to public perceptions in Europe, none

of these approaches led to a successful integration of immigrants. My point here is about

public perception, but also about the morality of those practices. Civic integration becomes

morally unacceptable whenever it is a form of illiberal cultural assimilation, as it is often the

case. And this leads to stage 4.

Stage 4: A proposal – back to human rights

The admission of the failure of both multiculturalism and civic integration as a way to deal

with immigrant groups in Europe invites a different approach. I want to suggest that the best

way out of the practical paradoxes of multicultural rights and supposedly civic integration

12

Page 13: Wp Cardoso

leads back to human rights, or to a non-culturalized view of human rights. In a way, this

means to go back to the model 48. However, because sixty years occurred since the

Universal Declaration was approved, I believe that the practice of human rights has revealed

to be more flexible and sensitive to difference than what was initially stated in human rights

text law.

The suggestion that the human rights approach is still the best way to deal with ethnic

diversity in Europe - and perhaps also in other places – requires at least two strands of

argument. The first one is practical and must establish that human rights alone, without

recourse to rights protecting specific minorities, are enough to deal with diversity without

incurring in the problems and paradoxes of both multiculturalism and false civic integration.

The second strand of argument is philosophical and it requires that human rights are not

definitely ethnocentric and that they may be presented as detached from specific western

doctrines regarding the definition of human nature. I will deal with each one of these two

strands of argument at a time.

Human rights text law has evolved over the years in order to accommodate the demands of

ethnic minorities. One example of this is the 1993 Declaration on the Rights of Persons

Belonging to National, Ethnic, Religious or Linguistic Minorities. This Declaration, like

other UN instruments, does not cancel the universal and general character of human rights,

but it draws the attention of governments and other agents in the international arena

(intergovernmental organizations, ONG’s) to the need to protect and promote the rights of

persons belonging to cultural minorities. However, the multiculturalist idea of special rights

for minorities is not taken into account and this aspect is consequential.

In practical terms, and from the vantage point of equal human rights, it is hard to justify, for

instance, polygamous marriages. By the same token, the much discussed case of female

genital mutilation performed on children before the age of consent and arranged marriages,

are clearly excluded. The former breaches the prohibition of inhuman or cruel treatment of

individuals. The latter trumps the principle that “Marriage shall be entered into only with the

free and full consent of the intending spouses” (Universal Declaration of Human Rights).

Nevertheless, many other demands by ethnic groups may be easily accommodated.

13

Page 14: Wp Cardoso

Imagine that a hindu living in Europe asks to be cremated in a open air pyre, rather than in a

closed crematory oven. Is it required, in order to have a moral assessment – and, in the end,

also a legal decision – about this demand to revert to multicultural rights, or to deny the

demand by invoking false civic integration? Certainly not. Human rights language and the

principle of non-discrimination is enough to justify that the wish to be cremated in a pyre is

attended and protected by law. The important requirement here is that this possibility is

given not just to members of the hindu community, but also to everyone who wishes to be

cremated in open air.

Take another case: the exemption of rules regarding animal slaughter for some groups of

Jews and Muslims. Unless one believes that non-human animals also have human rights, this

kind of exemptions can be accepted. However, the exemption has to be accorded to all, not

just to some specific groups. Recall that, in many parts of Europe, there’s the traditional

killing of the pig, bleeding the animal to death, which is perhaps not closely linked to the

Christian tradition but is nevertheless a time-honoured practice of great importance both

economically and for the cultural identity of the communities where it occurs. If Jews and

Muslims can bleed their animals to death, why can’t a peasant in Spain? The alternative to

the granting of this kind of rights is the idea that all should obey the existing general law

about animal slaughter. But, in that case, this should apply with no exceptions based on

cultural premises.

In spite of these examples, I don’t want to convey the impression that I am an anti-

multiculturalist in the sense of Brian Barry, since I prefer to describe myself as a post-

multiculturalist. Multiculturalist demands are not something to forget about and the work of

multiculturalist philosophers is of great importance. But multiculturalist demands – this is

my contention - should be re-interpreted in the language of human rights and they should be

connected with other kinds of demands by dominated or oppressed people. Using principles

of non-discrimination and equal treatment, the language of human rights may also meet these

other demands, such as those based on social class, or sex, or sexual preference, or handicap,

or lifestyle, and so on and so forth. And I mean non-discrimination and equal treatment

applying to all human beings, and to all citizens at the domestic level of states, regardless of

their communitarian belongings.

14

Page 15: Wp Cardoso

I will not say more about the practical aspects of the return to human rights as the best way

to deal with cultural diversity and I turn to the second question, namely the need to detach

human rights from its ethnocentricity or, to be more clear, from that kind of ethnocentric

reading in philosophy that deliberately obscures the universal role of human rights and

submits them to the radical “suspicion” of being only a product of a European and

Enlightened conception of man.

The traditional view on the justification of human rights links those rights with a specific

moral philosophy and philosophical anthropology. According to the traditional view human

rights are the rights of all human beings only by virtue of their humanity. This implies some

definition of men’s “humanity” and of the fundamental values that protect it. Thus, human

rights may be seen as a protection of agency or personhood (Alan Gewirth; James Griffin),

capabilities (Amartya Sen / Martha Nussbaum), or even basic needs (David Miller). All

these possibilities, different as they are, belong to the same strand of argument. They all try

to found human rights on the most fundamental human values that those rights are supposed

to protect.

Now there is a completely different view, which conceives of human rights as non-

foundational, but still an object for rational justification and argument. The basis of this view

was advanced by John Rawls in his contribution to the philosophy of international law. The

same view was recently further developed by Charles Beitz and Joseph Raz. According to

this view it belongs to the specific nature of human rights – as opposed to other kinds of

rights – their non-foundationality. In other words, human rights should not be confused with

fully justified moral rights. Sometimes this view endorsed by Rawls, Beitz or Raz is called

“the political or practical view”. I prefer to call it “the functional view” since its mains point

is the understanding of the very concept of human rights in terms of the functions of those

rights.

The main function of human rights in the international system is the limitation of the

external sovereignty of states. Human rights are those rights whose violation legitimises

some form of interference by states and international organizations in another state’s

sovereignty. This is the main point made by Rawls, Raz and Beitz. But one should add that

human rights perform other functions, both in the international system and at the intra-state

level. For instance, at the domestic level, human rights protect individuals against the state

15

Page 16: Wp Cardoso

and other powers and they are a sine qua non condition for the justification of political

obligation. The important point here is to call the attention to the fact that human rights do

perform these and other functions and that they are already part of our political and legal

landscape, in spite of the fact that there is no agreement – and, I suspect, thee will never be -

regarding their deepest philosophical foundation.*

So, what I have been suggesting here is that both at the level of its philosophical

underpinnings and political – and legal – practice, human rights provide the best framework

to deal with diversity. The language of human rights is already in place and it is less

contested that multiculturalism or civic integration (perhaps with the exception of China).

Moreover, this language is aimed at protecting all oppressed individuals, whether or not their

oppression is based on cultural bias.■

Bibliography

Barry, Brian (2001) Culture and Equality: An Egalitarian Critique of Multiculturalism,

Cambridge, Polity Press.

Beitz, Charles (2009), The Idea of Human Rights, Oxford, Oxford University Press.

Gewirth, A. (1982), Human Rights, Chicago, Chicago UP.

Glendon, Mary Ann (2001), A World Made New: Eleanor Roosevelt and the Universal

Declaration of Human Rights, New York, Random House.

Griffin, James (2008), On Human Rights, Oxford, Oxford UP.

Kymlicka, Will (1989) Liberalism, Community, and Culture, Oxford, Clarendon Press.

Kymlicka, Will (1995) Multicultural Citizenship: A Liberal Theory of Minority Rights,

Oxford, Clarendon Press.

Miller, David (2000), Citizenship and National Identity, Cambridge, Polity Press.

Miller, David (2007), National Responsibility and Global Justice, Oxford, Oxford

University Press.

Pogge, Thomas (2002), Human Rights and World Poverty, Cambridge, Polity Press.

Rawls, John (1999), The Law of Peoples, Cambridge, Ma., Harvard UP.

* There is a lot more to say about the functionalist account of human rights, but I will leave that for the discussion.

16

Page 17: Wp Cardoso

17

Raz, Joseph (2007), “Human Rights Without Foundations”, in

http://papers.ssrn.com/sol3/papers.cfm?abstract_id=999874

Rosas, João (2007), “Sociedade Multicultural: Conceitos e Modelos”, Relações

Internacionais, N.º 14, Junho 2007, pp. 47-56.

Taylor, Charles et alt. (1994), Multiculturalism: Examining the Politics of Recognition,

Princeton NJ, Princeton University Press.

Wenar, Leif (2005), “The Nature of Human Rights”, in Andreas Follesdal and Thomas

Pogge (eds.), Real World Justice: Grounds, Principles, Human Rights, and Social

Institutions, Springer.